Julian hefts the gauntlet:
I'm not sure why James thinks that we libertarians, so unsuccessful in
politics, have this kind of outsized influence on the culture, the
advent of Reason.tv notwithstanding. I think he means "cultural
libertarians," but these are not necessarily the same people who
self-identify as "libertarians" simpliciter. If anything, doesn't being
a committed member of a political movement mean, more or less by
definition, that you're not simply seeking meaning and satisfaction through "trivial novelties"?
Consider this Point One. Julian's right, here -- at least, the Ron Paul candidacy strikes me as the perfect example of how he's right. But notice who gets bent out of shape when Paul advocates politically libertarian positions but rejects culturally libertarian ones. Yes, there is some overlap -- see, e.g., abortion -- but in order for this conversation to make any sense (Julian also seems to acknowledge this), it must be possible to be a political libertarian in good standing without having to be a full-fledged cultural libertarian. But this reveals a certain tension. Yes, if you're a committed political libertarian active in journalism or even politics, you are eschewing the central cultural libertarian tenet that trivial novelties are in fact way more important and satisfying goods than those you get out of political activity. But let's guess at some percentages. I suspect the number of political libertarians working in politics-related fields is micronically smaller than the number of cultural libertarians leisuring along outside of politics. And this points to me toward the heart of the problem. Political libertarians have an outsized influence on the culture -- outsized, that is, relative to their actual political impact -- because they say 'the law has no right to prohibit you from doing x, y, or z', and oftentimes they are quite right, and what people hear is 'I have the right to do x, y, or z, and if I feel like it, therefore I should', suffering, from my perspective, at least, from not only faulty logic but bad choice making. (You might be surprised how lenient I end up being, here, but that's grist for another post and doesn't affect the argument.) The bottom line here is that, in the culture as it is today, political libertarianism translates, whether it wants to or not, into a line of argumentation that undermines what I think has to be the basic tenet of political libertarianism -- that there are things the government can't stop you from doing which you ought to be stopping yourself from doing. Today that maxim seems stupid to way more people than it seems smart to. That's a big problem for political libertarianism. It's the reason why there aren't any Barry Goldwaters walking around anymore, and it's at the root of the many fissures and weird contradictions within the Ron Paul movement. Moving along:
As for the substance of the claim, it strikes me as rather clearly false. Yes, an open and pluralistic culture means you can live as a frivolous novelty junkie, but I'm not seeing the case for why it means one must.
One might expect, on the contrary, that a wider range of lifestyles and
communities of interest would allow each of us to be more fully
committed to his own. Similarly, the idea that cultural libertarianism
"destroys" political libertarianism is far from obvious to me. Rather,
it seems that being able to really feel the pull of diverse conceptions
of the good—and perhaps having held a few different ones at different
times—might dispose people to be more circumspect about throwing state
support behind any one. Perhaps James means that the "habits of the
heart" inculcated by cultural libertarianism leave us all so dissolute
that we'll end up needing the state to look after us. That's a larger
claim than I want to take up here, but I don't think it checks out: As
I argue here,
for instance, the narrative that blames the collapse of inner-city
family structures on the perverse values of latte-sipping elites
doesn't really capture what's going on.
Consider this Point Two. Here Julian's not so right, although his argument is a strong one and in order to disagree with me on these issues it has to be made. A 'wider range of lifestyles and communities of interest' do in fact 'allow' fuller levels of 'commitment'. But they do not necessarily encourage, and (following Nozickian logic) they rarely enforce, fuller levels of commitment. In fact, 'commitment' has already emerged as the term by which we designate particularly profound levels of sustainedly consistent choicemaking -- but not necessarily anything more. 'Commitment' designates strong attachment, but still contingent attachment. Libertarianism pleasantly entrusts the duty and the responsibility for maintaining duties and responsibilities to free individuals. But on the cultural back end, it contributes to the erosion of reasons why free individuals conceive of their duties and responsibilities as undroppable. I'd rather have this than despotism, if forced to choose, but my point is we need to avoid forcing ourselves to make that choice, and that the easiest way to fall into that trap is to imagine that that choice is an either/or, binary problem.
But there's another twist too. Commitment itself isn't an on/off switch. So you can be both more fully committed to a lifestyle choice or community of interest while simultaneously amping up your recreational forays into the enjoyment of trivial novelties. Indeed that's the whole idea behind the civilizing effects of commerce. If the public goods we value are deliberately made trivial -- like, say, the Cadillac CTS -- then we may safely proliferate incommensurable and incompatible private goods satisfied by personal commitments without worrying that those desires will spill over into the public sphere and create oppressive, biased rules and regulations that cramp individual freedom. We need the public space to become filled with, or dominated by, trivial novelties in order to both restrain and protect private commitments. At least that's the logic of the argument. Julian is right that having had different conceptions of the good (or jobs, or sex partners, or sexualities, or whatever) at different times inspires a certain circumspection about institutionalizing any particular 'lifestyle preference' in the law. This is naturally because the ability to lifestyle-hop is cramped whenever the law tries to hold any one constant, or even privilege a mere handful. But more importantly, Julian overlooks the way that cultural-libertarian circumspection about importing comprehensive doctrines into politics and law is only one facet of a larger circumspection about the practice of politics generally. The same impulse that leads toward the good idea of not officializing ideologies and doctrines in political regimes leads toward the bad idea of turning over the practice of politics to centralized and efficient neutral political scientists, who will master the systems analysis that can manage the flows of resources that free individuals have permitted the government to worry about for them.
So this is where 'needing the state to look after us' comes in -- not because cultural libertarians are 'dissolute' necessarily -- although some certainly are -- but because cultural libertarianism inspires citizens as a matter of logic to seek goods that require freedom from politics, and, sometimes, the active destruction of politics. Julian's resistance to this pressure -- laudable as it is -- shows up again in his unwillingness to grant what Kerry Howley speaks of flatly as mobility rights. Whereas Kerry is unafraid of affirmatively disintegrating citizenship, Julian wants to keep it more or less intact while also accruing to individuals the material benefits of their moral right to consociate. This fissure among libertarians seems to me to be central to the dilemmas bandied about here. Yet cultural mobility rights language is inescapable, I think, as well, internal to a polity going down the cultural-libertarian road, and so a particular ideology does wind up being imported into the public sphere and institutionalized. The Rawlsian-libertarian argument here (shudder) is yeah, 'neutralism' or whatever may be an ideology, but it's better than all others, and here's an allegedly persuasive argument why. The problem though is that the terms of the plain Rawlsian argument center precisely on justifying cultural neutralism's 'betterness' on political grounds. Cultural neutralism is better because it's better suited to political liberalism. But, again, cultural neutralism pulls us away from the practice of politics. So on the left you get only one right, the right to do as you please, and on the right you get only one right, the right not to be at risk of terrorism. It's startling that conservatives endorse torture only when it's done by the government and liberals endorse it only when it's done by consenting adults. The same minimization of rights, and minimization of politics, is at work, and it's egged on by cultural libertarianism, which is compatible with both government torture and bedroom bloodletting.
None of which is to say that Julian's guilty of helping America turn into an S&M society. I instinctively agree that the values of the latte class are not to blame for the decay of the urban environment. But simply because the values and interests of the urban lower class and the values and interests of the urban upper class are different does not mean that they both don't translate into an active vested interest in minimizing political liberty and turning it over to administrative despotism, which, I would argue, they do.
And on one final note, just as I alleged that cultural libertarianism tends to undermine political liberalism, there is a strong case to be made that cultural liberalism likewise erodes political liberalism (as I've just suggested) and moreover that cultural conservatism damages the integrity of the premises of political conservatism. But that's another story.
Recent Comments